Popular Posts
-
The anthropological perspective on commodification Review of the Marxist school Before discussing the anthropological perspective, let...
-
The project called "The Need to Define Commodification" is being finalized and fully written up. Please check back for updates on ...
-
Use of commodification as an academic concept After scouring over many different academic articles that employ the notion of commodificati...
-
By Jeffrey R Oliver, Michigan State University with Lindon Robison Michigan State University Abstract Commodification is a term tha...
-
* Derived from Robison, Oliver & Frank 2015 and review of: Achtenberg, E. P., & Marcuse, P. (1986)...
-
Decommodifying lyrics I got thinking about celebrity attempts at decommodifying their images and song lyrics came to mind. Consider ...
-
Etymology of the term "commodity" from Online Etymology Dictionary. Click to follow link. commodity (n.) early 15c., &qu...
-
INTRODUCTION TO TABLE: Although there are concrete, established (dictionary) definitions of commodification, most of them rely on the mean...
-
Executive summary * Although commodification is a frequent topic of interest across many disciplines as diverse as linguistics, sociolo...
-
Introduction * Commodification is a frequently employed, yet highly contested topic in academic literature (Zaman 2006). For sociologists...
Friday, February 27, 2015
Esurance sends a message about decommodification...
TYPOLOGY OF COMMODIFICATION AND DECOMMODIFICATION
|
Achtenberg, E. P., & Marcuse, P. (1986). Toward the
decommodification of housing. Critical perspectives on housing, 474-483.
|
Bambra, C. (2005). Cash versus services:‘worlds of welfare’and
the decommodification of cash benefits and health care services. Journal
of social policy, 34(02), 195-213.
|
Bambra, C. (2006). Research Note: Decommodification and the
worlds of welfare revisited. Journal of European Social
Policy, 16(1), 73-80.
|
Batton, C., & Jensen, G. (2002). Decommodification and
homicide rates in the 20th-century United States. Homicide
Studies, 6(1), 6-38.
|
Bond, P. (2002). An answer to marketization: decommodification
and the assertion of rights to essential services. Multinational Monitor,
23(7/8), 14-17.
|
Bond, P. (2004). Water commodification and decommodification
narratives: Pricing and policy debates from Johannesburg to Kyoto to Cancun
and back.Capitalism Nature Socialism, 15(1), 7-25.
|
Bond, P. (2005). Globalisation/commodification or
deglobalisation/decommodification in urban South Africa. Policy
Studies, 26(3-4), 337-358.
|
Clasen, J., & Siegel, N. A. (Eds.). (2007). Investigating welfare state change: the'dependent
variable problem'in comparative analysis. Edward Elgar Publishing.
|
Cook, D. T. (2004). The commodification of childhood: The
children’s clothing industry and the rise of the child consumer. Duke
University Press.
|
Dale, G. (2010). Social democracy, embeddedness and decommodification:
on the conceptual innovations and intellectual affiliations of Karl Polanyi.
New political economy, 15(3), 369-393.
|
Dickens, P. (1985). Housing, states, and localities. Taylor
& Francis.
|
Esping-Andersen, G. (1987). Citizenship and socialism:
decommodification and solidarity in the welfare state. Stagnation and
Renewal in Social Policy: The Rise and Fall of Policy Regimes, London:
Sharpe.
|
Esping-Andersen, G. (1988). Decommodification and work absence
in the welfare state.
|
Gal, J. (2004). Decommodification and beyond: a comparative
analysis of work-injury programmes. Journal of European Social Policy, 14(1),
55-69.
|
Gaukroger, S. (1986). Romanticism and decommodification: Marx's
conception of socialism. Economy and Society, 15(3), 287-333.
|
Gran, B. (1997). Three worlds of old-age decommodification?: A
comparative analysis of old-age support using the Luxembourg income study.
Journal of Aging Studies, 11(1), 63-79.
|
Halewood, C., & Hannam, K. (2001). Viking heritage tourism:
authenticity and commodification. Annals of tourism research, 28(3), 565-580.
|
Heller, M. (2003). Globalization, the new economy, and the
commodification of language and identity. Journal of sociolinguistics, 7(4),
473-492.
|
Henderson, G. (2004). 'Free' food, the local production of
worth, and the circuit of decommodification: a value theory of the surplus.
Environment and Planning D, 22(4), 485-512.
|
Holden, C. (2003). Decommodification and the workfare
state. Political Studies Review, 1(3), 303-316.
|
Huo, J., Nelson, M., & Stephens, J. D. (2008).
Decommodification and activation in social democratic policy: resolving the
paradox. Journal of European Social Policy, 18(1), 5-20.
|
Hyman, R. (2007). Labour, markets and the future of" decommodification".
Hans-Böckler-Stiftung.
|
Kaiser, C. P. (1998). Dimensions of culture, distributive
principles, and decommodification: Implications for employee absence
behavior. The Journal of Socio-Economics, 27(5), 551-564.
|
La Grange, A., & Pretorius, F.
(2005). Shifts along the decommodification-commodification continuum:
Housing delivery and state accumulation in Hong Kong. Urban Studies, 42(13),
2471-2488.
|
Lewis, J. (1992). Gender and the development of welfare regimes.
Journal of European social policy, 2(3), 159-173.
|
Murie, A. (2005). The dynamics of social exclusion and
neighborhood decline: welfare regimes, decommodification, housing, and urban
inequality. Cities of Europe: Changing Contexts, Local Arrangements, and the
Challenge to Urban Cohesion, 151-169.
|
Ray, R., Gornick, J. C., & Schmitt, J. (2010). Who cares?
Assessing generosity and gender equality in parental leave policy designs in
21 countries. Journal of European Social Policy, 20(3), 196-216.
|
Robison, L., Oliver, J., & Frank, K. (2015). Commodity and
Relational Good Exchanges: Commodification and Decommodification. In 2015
Allied Social Science Association (ASSA) Annual Meeting, January 3-5, 2015,
Boston, Massachusetts (No. 189690). Agricultural and Applied
Economics Association.
|
Room, G. (2000). Commodification and decommodification: a
developmental critique. Policy & Politics, 28(3), 331-351.
|
Salzman, J., & Ruhl, J. B. (2000). Currencies and the
commodification of environmental law. Stanford Law Review, 607-694.
|
Scruggs, L., & Allan, J. (2003, August). Trends in welfare
state decommodification in eighteen advanced industrial democracies,
1972-2000. In Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association.
|
Scruggs, L., & Allan, J. (2004). Welfare state
decommodification and poverty in advanced industrial democracies. In Trabalho
apresentado na 14a International Conference of Europeanists, Palmer House
Hilton, Chicago, IL (pp. 11-13).
|
Scruggs, L., & Allan, J. (2006). Welfare-state
decommodification in 18 OECD countries: a replication and
revision. Journal of European Social Policy, 16(1), 55-72.
|
Sesia, P. (2003). Repeasantization and decommodification of indigenous
agriculture: Coffee, corn, and food security in Oaxaca. The social relations
of Mexican commodities: Power, production, and place, 81-126.
|
Sharp, L. A. (2000). The commodification of the body and its
parts. Annual Review of Anthropology, 287-328.
|
Soron, D., & Laxer, G. (2006). Thematic Introduction
Decommodification, Democracy and the Battle for the Commons. Not For Sale
Decommodifying Public Life, 1, 15-35.
|
Suddaby, R., & Greenwood, R. (2001). Colonizing knowledge:
Commodification as a dynamic of jurisdictional expansion in professional
service firms. Human relations, 54(7), 933-953.
|
Thrift, N. (2006). Re-inventing invention: new tendencies in
capitalist commodification. Economy and Society, 35(02), 279-306.
|
Timothy Burke. (1996). Lifebuoy Men, Lux Women: commodification,
consumption, and cleanliness in modern Zimbabwe. Duke University Press.
|
Ungerson, Clare (1997) Social politics and the
commodification of care. Social
Politics, 4, (3), 362-381.
|
Vail, J. (2010). Decommodification and egalitarian political
economy. Politics & Society, 38(3), 310-346.
|
Walby, S. (2001). From gendered welfare state to gender regimes:
national differences, convergence, or restructuring?. Gender and Society
Group, Stockholm University, 17.
|
Western, B. (1989). Decommodification and the Transformation of
Capitalism: welfare state development in seventeen OECD countries. Journal of
Sociology, 25(2), 200-221.
|
Willmott, H. (1995). Managing the Academics: Commodification and
Control in the Development of University Education in the UK. Human
Relations, 48(9), 993-1027.
|
Zaman, H. (2006). Breaking the iron wall: Decommodification and
immigrant women's labor in Canada. Lexington Books.
|
Monday, February 23, 2015
Globalization, globalism and decommodification
By Jeff Oliver
What is the connection between globalization, globalism and decommodification? In 2006, Zaman captured the essentials of these connections quite well. The book is worth reading for anyone that is interested in the intersection between social rights and globalism, social rights and immigration or globalism and immigration. I am interested in all such intersections. For several months I have been seeing the treatment of migrants as a product of commodification and neoliberalism.
While globalism and commodification certainly are not synonymous (I fear that some are beginning to make this mistake...), globalism, especially as defined by those like Zaman, tends to bring commodification with it wherever it goes. With neoliberalism as the prime political-economic agenda of globalism, the market (and as an extension market-value) come to occupy a larger place in globalized societies. If we define commodification as an increase in the centrality of markets and market value in society (Holden 2003, Bond 2004, 2005, Vail 2010) then commodification would seem to naturally follow globalism almost like its shadow. This is because of the difficulty in increasing the emphasis on markets without becoming commodified (at least by the definition that commodification is an increasing emphasis on the market and market value!).
Finally, there is a great paradox in this commodification of migrants as migrants often seem to fall on a "double edged sword of commodification"--be lazy and unproductive if they do not succeed economically and a threat to native born jobs if they do succeed economically (see Gold 2010).
What is the connection between globalization, globalism and decommodification? In 2006, Zaman captured the essentials of these connections quite well. The book is worth reading for anyone that is interested in the intersection between social rights and globalism, social rights and immigration or globalism and immigration. I am interested in all such intersections. For several months I have been seeing the treatment of migrants as a product of commodification and neoliberalism.
Commodification as an emphasis on markets/market value
Zaman ties these things all together quite nicely. It is hard to do justice to the entire book in a few sentences, but if I were to make that attempt, I would first borrow a sentence from Zaman: "globalism can be described as neo-liberal globalism" (Zaman 2006, 4 see also Otero & Jugenitz 2006). In other words, globalism is about increasingly enlarging the place of markets and market value in a society which has the (unintended?) side-effect of decreasing the intrinsic or non-market value of things in society. There is a vast discussion debating and developing this idea (Room 2000, Holden 2003, Bond 2004, 2005, Scruggs & Allan 2006, Vail 2010).While globalism and commodification certainly are not synonymous (I fear that some are beginning to make this mistake...), globalism, especially as defined by those like Zaman, tends to bring commodification with it wherever it goes. With neoliberalism as the prime political-economic agenda of globalism, the market (and as an extension market-value) come to occupy a larger place in globalized societies. If we define commodification as an increase in the centrality of markets and market value in society (Holden 2003, Bond 2004, 2005, Vail 2010) then commodification would seem to naturally follow globalism almost like its shadow. This is because of the difficulty in increasing the emphasis on markets without becoming commodified (at least by the definition that commodification is an increasing emphasis on the market and market value!).
Other definitions of commodification
There are other definitions of commodification, however. Although these will not be discussed in depth at this time (see the post in this blog on "Straightening out definitions of commodification and decommodification), I would argue that all of these definitions stem out of the broader idea (and more inclusive definition of the term "commodification"): any process that increases the commodity component of an object (be it a society, a person, an exchange or a material or immaterial object). Consequently, Zaman's (2006) assertion seems to be supported--globalism brings with it an increased focus on things that have worth in a market (commodities). We must therefore only make the tiny leap from that idea to the idea that the esteem of non-commodities is simultaneously reduced in society (it is theoretically possible for the value of both to increase, although one might question how often that actually occurs in practice...).Intersections of commodification and migration
If commodification and globalism are so tightly joined, then it becomes easy to see how these might intersect with migration. Migrants generally feel low status in society and generally struggle to find a place and a space in their new countries (Gold 2010). In the wake of globalism, migrants are often expected (whether it is done consciously or unconsciously) to justify their presence in a new country based on their market value. In this way, migrants are commodified. Some countries (without doing extensive research New Zealand comes to mind...) have a system down that "quantifies" the market worth of a potential migrant down to every last detail and this is the system used to determine admission to the country. Likewise, we hear stories even in the US of the "high worth" migrants that get moved to the front of the line because of "who they are" meaning how wealthy they are or how valuable their services will be (STEM educated PhDs for example...).Finally, there is a great paradox in this commodification of migrants as migrants often seem to fall on a "double edged sword of commodification"--be lazy and unproductive if they do not succeed economically and a threat to native born jobs if they do succeed economically (see Gold 2010).
Summary observations
In the wake of globalism, migrants are asked to navigate their new country vis-à-vis their market value. However, this often exacerbates their low status as they are seen either as a threat if they succeed economically or as lazy and a drain on society if they do not succeed economically. Additionally, other definitions of commodification (described in the blog post, "Straightening out definitions of commodification and decommodification") imply that migrants become objectified, dehumanized or alienated from their intrinsic worth as a person. Zaman (2006) has partially undertaken a study of what it means for migrants to become decommodified in a world of neoliberal globalism. This book is a great read for those interested in the intersections of migration, globalism and commodification. Additionally, there is room to expand, think through and further push on Zaman's ideas.
Specifically, definitions of commodification and decommodification are still largely under-developed and often applied almost exclusively to the idea of state intervention and welfare. While decommodification can be linked to the state's actions in reducing the emphasis on the market, there are many applications to discuss decommodification and migrants outside of that context. For example, the way migrants are admitted to a country can either commodify or decommodify them, the way they are treated by the native born segment, or the way they are portrayed in the media can all "objectify" migrants or emphasize the value they have based on their intrinsic human worth.
Works cited
Bond, P. (2004). Water
commodification and decommodification narratives: Pricing and policy debates
from Johannesburg to Kyoto to Cancun and back.Capitalism Nature Socialism,
15(1), 7-25.
Bond, P. (2005).
Globalisation/commodification or deglobalisation/decommodification in urban
South Africa. Policy Studies, 26(3-4), 337-358.
Gold, S. J. (2010). The
store in the hood: A century of ethnic business and conflict. Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers.
Holden, C. (2003).
Decommodification and the workfare state. Political Studies Review, 1(3),
303-316.
Otero, G. and H. Jugenitz (2006). "Forging New Democracies: Indigenous Struggles for Autonomy" in Laxer, G. and D. Soron (eds.) Not for Sale: Decommodifying Public Life, University of Toronto Press, Higher Education Division.
Room, G. (2000). Commodification and decommodification: a developmental critique. Policy & Politics, 28(3), 331-351.
Room, G. (2000). Commodification and decommodification: a developmental critique. Policy & Politics, 28(3), 331-351.
Vail, J. (2010).
Decommodification and egalitarian political economy. Politics & Society,
38(3), 310-346.
Zaman, H. (2006). Breaking
the iron wall: Decommodification and immigrant women's labor in Canada.
Lexington Books.
Friday, February 20, 2015
Commodification, decommodification and social rights
Should we be free to enjoy our life in a way that we do not
depend on market forces? In the seminal work The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Espling-Anderson (1990)
provided a definition of “decommodification” that is very popular in academia
to the present (Bambra 2005, 2006; Scruggs & Allan 2006; Huo, Nelson &
Stephens 2008). Because this definition focuses on the way market forces can
impede social rights, it may be tempting to say that commodification (the
opposite of decommodification) should be seen as a sort of “enemy” to social
rights, and should consequently be minimized, but to what extent?
Decommodification –freedom to enjoy social rights without bowing to the
market
At its heart, Espling-Anderson’s argument is that social
rights and social stratification “are shaped by nexus of state and market in
the distribution system" (Esping-Anderson 1990, 4). The reason this can be
called “decommodification” is because social rights diminish a person’s status
as a “commodity”—and the state and the market are the two major forces that can
impact that status.
Hou, Nelson & Stephens (2008) paraphrase Espling-Anderson by saying that decommodification means "exit from the labour market with little or no loss of income" (2008). This may seem incomplete or contradictory, but it is right on target with the point Espling-Anderson (1990) seems to be making: that “outstanding criterion for social rights must be the degree to which they permit people to make their living standard independent of market forces”. Perhaps it is Espling-Anderson’s point, or maybe it is an extension of it to say that the fundamental consideration in balancing the market and the state is the degree to which human beings are able to enjoy some basic standard of living without having to bow to powerful market forces.
At first, this conjures to mind ideas about the “neoliberal
project” –a sort of “market über alles”
political economy. As Espling-Anderson (1990) points out, contemporary
neoliberalism is little more than the political economic project of favoring
and enacting neoclassical economic principles in a country. Many have written
about neoliberalism as a project of conquest—a sort of neo-colonialism—that ends
up benefitting wealthy elites in the name of “trickle-down economics” (Szirmai 2005, Harvey 2007, Duménil
& Levy 2011). While this cannot be undertaken in full in this article,
those familiar with this literature may see a connection between Espling-Anderso’s
(1990) notion of decommodification and the way that state deregulation of the
market can decrease social rights—specifically for the poor or underprivileged.
In
short, “commodifying” people—allowing the market to become so important in
society that people are only “worth” what they can produce or exchange in the
market—has the potential to almost destroy social rights for non-elites in
society. Therefore, are we to conclude that commodification is dehumanizing and
should be extinguished?
The paradox of commodification as “undesirable”
While it may seem easy to argue against commodification as
it is an enemy to social rights, I am reminded of a statement I once heard from
Dr. Lawrence Bush (University
Distinguished Professor of Sociology at Michigan State University) referring to
bureaucracy that seems to apply equally well to commodification. We all like it! Commodification moves
exchanges into regulated, efficient and predictable markets. We like that we
can have our labor “monetized” based on certain standards, precedents or
conventions. It is easy and predictable to know and compare prices and use
money—the monetized “version” or “substitute” of our labor—to buy products. We
like that we can see real estate listings with prices when buying a home.
Markets can be very efficient and it seems unlikely that any of us would sign
up to have markets completely banned. So as much as we do not want markets to
get “out of control” or take over our lives, we must not forget that we all
look to them for their redeeming qualities of transparency and efficiency.
Conclusion—what should the balance be?
Do not misunderstand that I am arguing in favor of markets.
Rather, I am making the point that what most of us are really looking for is a
balance between state power and market power. Espling-Anderson (1990) provided
the theoretical foundation for conversations that center around finding that
balance. Favoring the market in a society can lead to the undesirable outcome
of commodification of human beings. My own research on the neoliberal project
in Colombia in the 1990s supports the idea that favoring the market can
commodify people.
Many indigenous people in Colombia have had their “inalienable”
lands sold off to transnational corporations. For many of these individuals,
land is not a commodity, but a part of who they are—a part of their identity. Even
putting a price tag on land is a commodifying process in the eyes of many of
these indigenous people. The question then remains, what is the role of
government—or what should it be—in regulating the reach and influence of
markets. In 1984, the United States government made it illegal to sell your own
organs (National Organ Transplant Act). This is an expression of the way
governments can override market forces in favor of the “decommodification” of
people. In other words, governments can and have stepped in to situations that
will make people lose their “humanity” and become more like a commodity. One
might argue that prostitution laws have the same desired outcome—the keep
people from selling themselves like a commodity. Where and how this line must
be drawn is largely a matter of perception and culture that must be decided by
stake holders in any given context.
Works Cited
Esping-Andersen,
Gosta. 1990. The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Princeton University Press.
Scruggs, L., & Allan, J. (2006). Welfare-state
decommodification in 18 OECD countries: a replication and revision. Journal
of European Social Policy, 16(1), 55-72.
Bambra, C. (2006). Research Note: Decommodification and the
worlds of welfare revisited. Journal of European Social Policy, 16(1),
73-80.
Bambra, C. (2005). Cash versus services:‘worlds of welfare’and
the decommodification of cash benefits and health care services. Journal
of social policy, 34(02), 195-213.
Huo, J., Nelson, M., & Stephens, J. D. (2008).
Decommodification and activation in social democratic policy: resolving the
paradox. Journal of European Social Policy, 18(1),
5-20.
Szirmai, A. (2005).The Dynamics
of Socio-Economic Development: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.
Harvey, D. (2007). Neoliberalism
as creative destruction. American Academy
of Political and Social Science, 610. 22-44.
Duménil, G. and Levy, D. (2011).
The crisis of neoliberalism. Harvard University Press. Cambridge, Mass
Wednesday, February 18, 2015
Straightening out definitions of commodification and decommodification
Introduction
Commodification and decommodification have been observed to
be terms whose definitions are “frequently contested but not contradictory”
(Zaman 2006, 8). Yet, can there be little argument that in practice commodification
and decommodification are used in many different ways. (Even Zaman (2006, ix) notes that commodification needs further exploration and that decommodification is an "under-developed" concept). For example, does
commodification mean that something has been standardized, objectified vs.
regarded primarily in terms of its intrinsic worth as suggested by scholars
such as Suddaby & Greenwood (2001) and Heller (2003)? Or is commodification
a cultural increase in the place commodities have in a given society (Burke
1996, Cook 2004, Thrift 2006)? Does commodification mean that something is
exchanged in a market (vs. non-market) setting (Willmott 1995, Halewood &
Hannam 2001)? Or does commodification mean payment for informal services
(Ungerson 1997, Williams & Windebank 2003)?
If the diversity of those definitions is problematic,
discussions of decommodification become even more problematic as they are often
not the opposite of commodification (as logic would argue they should be). For example, decommodification is often
seen as exchanges taking place in informal settings or as state regulation. In
the case of the latter, there is an abundance of literature on
decommodification and the welfare state ( Orloff 1993, Savolainen 2000, Scruggs
& Allan 2006). Ironically, unless one defines commodification as “state deregulation,”
this definition (decommodification as state regulation) becomes somewhat
illogical—or at least somewhat logically inconsistent.
What should the definition of decommodification be?
This is difficult to posit without first having a
well-established definition of commodification (of which decommodification
should logically be the opposite). First, however, it should be noted that many
scholars writing about decommodification and the welfare state are careful to
use wording that does not conflate state regulation with decommodification. For
example, Huber, Ragin and Stephens (1993) describe the “decommodifying effect of (the) welfare state…”
(emphasis added). Brady, Beckfield & Seeleib-Kaiser (2005) denote
decommodification as one of three measures of the welfare state (rather than
asserting that decommodification is synonymous with the welfare state or state regulation).
Certainly state regulation is a highly related topic to
decommodification. However, to say that state regulation is decommodification misses the underlap that occurs between state
deregulation and decommodification. For example, think of the way
commodification has been described as objectification of something. An object
can become regarded primarily vis-à-vis its measurable
worth vs. its intrinsic value (some scholars would say that commodification
is when something’s use value is displaced by its market value [Willmott 1995]).
This objectification can exist in a way that is completely independent of state
regulation or deregulation. This is not to say that state regulation cannot
impact conceptions of commodification or decommodification, but commodification
and decommodification are largely social (Sharp 2000). Markets are socially
constructed, and commodities are only deemed so to be based on social
perceptions. Consequently, commodification
is a social construct, and whether or not something is seen as a commodity
may be influenced by a host of factors, of which state intervention is only one
aspect.
In partial support of Zaman’s point, the many definitions of
commodification, as described in the first paragraph, are not completely
contradictory. However, they are often imprecise, creating confusion in their
usage. Consider defining commodification in a way that is consistent with the
term “commodity” (Robison,
Oliver & Frank 2015). In fact, even Karl Marx, the "father" of commodification declared that because the commodity is the most basic unit in capitalist societies, "Our investigation must...begin with the analysis of a commodity" (Marx 1967). If a commodity is something that is generally
mass produced, exchanged in a market, and valued largely for its form, quality and
function rather than the specific individuals that produce or consume it, then
what is commodification? Simply put, it is any process that converts something
into an object that is exchanged in a market and primarily valued for its form,
quality and function rather than the specific individuals involved in the
production or consumption of that object.
Consequently, it becomes apparent that the definitions given
in the introduction are not all inaccurate, but often imprecise or not all
inclusive. For example, the definition of commodification as “objectification”
is not incorrect, but only takes in part of the definition (converting
something into an object with measurable values rather than intrinsic worth).
The definition of commodification as a cultural increase in the preoccupation with
commodities in a society certainly is useful as it employs commodities in the definition.
In this case the “thing” that is commodified is societal preoccupations. In
general, things in society are given more worth or are more highly esteemed if
they are seen as commodities. Additionally, saying that commodification is a
conversion to market (vs. non-market) exchange is at least partially correct as
commodities are exchanged in markets. However, it has been noted that certain
special cases of decommodification can take place in market settings as well—a point
that will not be thoroughly undertaken in this piece but can has been taken up
in Robison,
Oliver & Frank (2015).
The last definition of commodification implies that payment
for informal services can be seen as commodification. While this can be true, it is certainly not
necessarily the case. The exchange of money corresponds highly to the purchase
of commodities, but money can be exchanged for non-commodities. If one
purchases friendship or sexual intimacy it is said to “commodify” those
objects. In other words, buying something with money tends to commodify things
that were not previously commodities. However, consider the caring friend or
family member that buys your freedom with money. This has the opposite effect
of restoring your value as a human being rather than an object that could be
owned like a commodity (personal conversation with Lindon Robison December
2014).
Additionally, definitions of decommodification (or commodification) will have different a different focus based on the unit of analysis. For example, "commodifying" a person might mean to treat them like a commodity, while commodification of culture or society might focus on the way commodity exchange is emphasized or valued in a society (as well as possible discussions of reasons why they are valued).
Additionally, definitions of decommodification (or commodification) will have different a different focus based on the unit of analysis. For example, "commodifying" a person might mean to treat them like a commodity, while commodification of culture or society might focus on the way commodity exchange is emphasized or valued in a society (as well as possible discussions of reasons why they are valued).
Conclusion
While it can be argued that the current definitions of
commodification are “frequently contested but not contradictory” (Zaman 2006, 8),
it should be noted that the current definitions are often incomplete. This is
very academically precarious as notions of commodification appear to be
conflated with other things such as dehumanization and state deregulation. While
these are related terms, it is very risky to confuse them with the basic
definition of commodification as any process that increase the position of
commodities in human exchanges or perceptions. Additionally, the many varying
definitions of commodification appear to be spilling over into the logical
opposite of commodification—decommodification. If the definition of
commodification is being contested, how can we agree on the definition of its
opposite? Returning to the basic definition of a commodity in finding a definition
for commodification (as suggested in Robison,
Oliver & Frank [2015]) is recommended in order to have inclusive definitions
of commodification that will not create further confusion in academic studies.
Works cited
Brady, D., Beckfield, J., & Seeleib-Kaiser, M. (2005).
Economic globalization and the welfare state in affluent democracies,
1975–2001. American Sociological Review, 70(6), 921-948.
Huber, E., Ragin, C., & Stephens, J. D.
(1993). Social democracy, Christian democracy, constitutional structure, and
the welfare state. American journal of Sociology, 711-749.
Marx, 1967 Capital, Volume 1 New York: International
Publishers
Orloff, A. S. (1993). Gender and the social
rights of citizenship: The comparative analysis of gender relations and welfare
states. American sociological review, 303-328.
Scruggs, L., & Allan, J. (2006).
Welfare-state decommodification in 18 OECD countries: a replication and
revision. Journal of European Social Policy, 16(1),
55-72.
Zaman, H. (2006). Breaking the iron wall:
Decommodification and immigrant women's labor in Canada. Lexington Books.
Tuesday, February 10, 2015
Corruption and social resource theory
Social resource theory (and social
exchange theory in general) posits that human interaction can be seen as exchanges
of tangible and intangible resources. While corruption has been discussed in
great detail in academic literature, it is interesting to think about
corruption through the lens of social resource theory. In doing so, one need
look no further than Herbert Spencer and his work The Man vs. the State: Six
Essays on Government, Society and Freedom (available online here). Spencer notes that
societies choose how much of their freedom they give over to the state. His
argument was (allow me to paraphrase) that people give their freedoms over to
the state when a situation arises that seems too big for them to handle on their
own. This becomes cyclical as the state gains power that the people have
forfeited, so the next time a large problem arises, the people need the state
even more and give it more power, and the cycle continues. One might say that
Spencer was arguing that people entrust the state with their personal
freedoms.
Entrusting individuals with rights
or privileges once belonging to others lays the foundation for corruption.
Taking a social resources approach, we might say that people give their rights
and privileges (intangible resources) in exchange for greater efficiency (here,
one might observe the irony of this observation which will be explained later),
peace of mind, or more power to “get things done”. This should not be hastily
dismissed. After all, would you rather coordinate military defense as a
collective of individuals, or put it into the hands of the government?
Therefore, although one might not think of the government as highly efficient
(and perhaps it is not in many cases) there are things like military protection
that would be highly inefficient if left to the people. The efficiency we are
talking about here is mainly an extension of the government’s control of what
Spencer would call vast resources (available here).
The idea that people give their
intangible resources, including rights and privileges, to the government brings
to mind a number of opportunities for corruption.
In Franz Kafka's book The Trial, Josef K. learns that he is to stand trial for crimes he did not know he committed. A guard informs him that his personal possessions will be taken and held until after the trial. The guard then gives him the bad news: trials "these days" are taking so long that the possessions will probably eventually all be sold off. He further comments that Josef will still get the proceeds from the sale, but that they will likely be very meager. The guard then makes the astute observation that "sales aren't based on the size of the offer but on the size of the bribe".
In Franz Kafka's book The Trial, Josef K. learns that he is to stand trial for crimes he did not know he committed. A guard informs him that his personal possessions will be taken and held until after the trial. The guard then gives him the bad news: trials "these days" are taking so long that the possessions will probably eventually all be sold off. He further comments that Josef will still get the proceeds from the sale, but that they will likely be very meager. The guard then makes the astute observation that "sales aren't based on the size of the offer but on the size of the bribe".
Think of this: if I sell something on eBay, there is a certain price that that thing will sell for based on its value as a commodity plus any socio-emotional value. However, if I somehow become entrusted with your property, value can be lost through bribery. Take for example a bike worth $1000. This is its value as a commodity, plus it has socio-emotional based on its brand, or maybe it is a vintage bike that a lot of people have fond memories about, but all things considered, let us say the value is $1000. That is the amount I expect to make if I sell the bike, let’s say on eBay. Finally, let us suppose in scenario 1 I list the bike on eBay and it sells for the expected amount, $1000.
Now, if I entrust it to you, there can be a different
outcome. The buyer can bribe you to sell the bike for less. It is not your bike
and any amount of money you make is icing on the cake because you have nothing
invested in the bike and are not the owner of it (it has no commodity or
socio-emotional value for you because you do not own it). At some point, you
will be willing to sell the bike for a lower price based on a certain level of
bribe. Let us say that for $100, you will sell the bike for $750. The buyer
only had to spend $850 (saving $150 over what they would have otherwise paid),
you are up $100; the only person who loses out is me as the bike’s owner. Now,
you have to explain to me why you could only sell the bike for $750 and you
make up some story about how times are tough and no one was “biting” at the
higher price point or whatever.
The
point is that when someone is entrusted with something, they can breach that trust to get personal gain.
Is public trust an intangible resource?
The words of the guard bring to mind
countless incidents of corruption throughout the world. At the heart of corruption
is the idea that someone has breached public trust (Jain 2001). For example, we
hear of public officials taking bribes, hiring friends, funneling money into
friends’ companies, embezzling funds and so on. In many of these cases, it
appears that the corruption mostly has to do with getting gain in terms of tangible
resources. However, there is more to it than that. One must also consider the
intangible resources involved. For example, is public trust a resource? Do
corrupt officials steal or at least misuse the trust that was given them as an
intangible resource?
In order to answer that question, one might simply ask if the official would have been able to extract the same benefit without having the public’s trust. Often the answer is no. The way public trust is (or is not) an intangible resource is an area that might be further investigated in connection with social resource theory. If it is not a resource, then what is it? For example, is it simply a social situation facilitating the exchange of resources in certain ways?
In order to answer that question, one might simply ask if the official would have been able to extract the same benefit without having the public’s trust. Often the answer is no. The way public trust is (or is not) an intangible resource is an area that might be further investigated in connection with social resource theory. If it is not a resource, then what is it? For example, is it simply a social situation facilitating the exchange of resources in certain ways?
Economic applications of corruption and social resource theory
Additionally, one might observe other
potential areas for future research. For example, how does corruption relate to
Pareto optimality? For example, consider a situation that is not Pareto
optimal. We do not call all such situations corruption. The Great Recession of
2007/8 brought about some discussion throughout the world about Pareto
Optimality. For example, could not the situation of many people be improved a
little bit without really making the wealthy worse off? (Or, some would argue
it would even be fine if the wealthy were a little worse off…) This does not
mean that the wealthy are corrupt. However, corrupt individuals seem to act in
a way that is at the heart of a Pareto “inefficient” situation. Like the person
entrusted to sell the bike, corrupt officials will take a personal gain that
results in a greater loss than that gain for others. In other words, they would
take a bribe of $1,000 that would cost others $20,000. This could be done
through hiring friends that are not truly qualified to do complicated jobs, or
through giving work to friends’ companies and paying them much more than they
would otherwise make. A notable example is the Sochi 2014 Olympic Games. The $50
billion spent on the Sochi Olympics is reported to be higher than all other
Olympic winter games combined with approximately a third of that sum lost to “rampant
corruption, embezzlement and kickbacks” (Berman
2014). In this way, corruption makes everyone worse off than they would
have been. In Sochi, the people will now be stuck with a multi-billion dollar
bill that was the result of corruption.
Corruption can also be related to
game theory (economics) or the theory of social situations (psychology). For
example, think of a “prisoner’s dilemma” game in which the decisions of all
players on a team are entrusted to a single player who gets to decide what
everyone else on the team will choose to do. Now suppose that the decision
maker gets an incentive for breaching the trust of the players. It may be that
the decision maker earns 5 points for a decision that costs the team 10 points,
but if the decision maker doesn’t breach trust, they (the decision maker) get
nothing, or a lesser incentive.
Ethical considerations
All things considered, corruption often occurs when a
public official acts in a way that will create an increased personal benefit,
even if it is at the detriment of others. At what point is getting ahead, or
amassing gains inappropriate for a public official?
There are many philosophical opportunities to discuss
this question; however, morality is often defined by social consensus. In other
words, we do not hear of corruption when no one is opposed to known actions
that took place (a separate issue would be corrupt acts that have not been
discovered yet). It may be that because corruption involves a breach of public
trust, public opinion about the allegedly corrupt acts plays a big role in
determining if certain actions are corrupt. In common language: who determines
what is corrupt? Those who have a vested interest in a given corrupt act. Who
cares if a public park could not be built because a public official took a
bribe from a high-rise apartment developer? Those who paid tax dollars and
voted to have the park built.
Ergo, while a full treatise on the philosophical considerations
is not parsimonious at this time, it can be said that social consensus plays a
large role in determining what is and is not corruption.
Conclusion
In short, there are many potential ways to think about
breaches of trust as related to social resource theory. These breaches of trust
are often motivated by tangible resources. However, what are the intangible
resources that are at work? Should public trust be seen as an intangible
resource? Additionally, what are the economic implications of explaining
corruption through social resource theory? How might game theory and Pareto
optimality be related? How might they be extended given these ideas about
corruption? Finally, there are many philosophical and ethical questions that
accompany a discussion of corruption and social resource theory. These
questions may seem peripheral; however, without addressing these ethical
questions, one will not even know where to draw the boundary of corruption. In
other words, corruption cannot fully be described without knowing where it
starts and stops (which are essential in understanding what corruption is and
is not).
OTHER WORKS CITED NOT LINKED IN TEXT
Jain, A. K. (2001). Corruption: A review. Journal of
economic surveys, 15(1), 71-121.
Kafka, F. (1998) The Trial. New York: Schocken Books.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)